A QUICK INTRO TO RATIONAL IGNORANCE AND RATIONAL IRRATIONALITY
1. This stuff pertains to public choice theory, which is defined by Wikipedia as: ” the use of modern economic tools to study problems that traditionally are in the province of political science. From the perspective of political science, it is the subset of positive political theory that models voters, politicians, and bureaucrats as mainly self-interested.”
2. An important point for much of the theory of public choice in democracies is the fact that the probability that any individual’s vote will affect the outcome of the election is generally negligible. For example, in U.S. presidential elections, the probability that your vote will affect the election’s outcome is comparable to that of winning the lottery seven times in a row. This is because your vote only makes a difference if all the other votes happen to be exactly tied, so that your vote turns out to be the deciding vote – or perhaps if your vote happens to be the one leading to an exact tie!
3. RATIONAL IGNORANCE: According to Wikipedia, “The term was coined by Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy”. Wiki sez: “Rational ignorance occurs when the cost of educating oneself on an issue exceeds the potential benefit that the knowledge would provide.” Applied to democracy, voters are to be expected to be rationally ignorant about the issues they vote on. This is because, since their vote almost certainly won’t change policy, they have nothing to gain from making an informed vote rather than an uninformed one. On the other hand, the cost of informing themselves is considerable. Some people enjoy informing themselves about such issues, but they are a small minority.
4. Empirically, voters really are very ignorant about politics and economics. They are least ignorant about the aspects of politics that are the most entertaining.
5. Donald Wittman, in The Myth of Democratic Failure, has defended democracy against many of the usual criticisms from public choice theorists. One argument he makes in the book is that, because of the miracle of aggregation, rational ignorance is not actually a problem: provided that people are merely ignorant and not systematically biased, their mistakes should cancel out. Also, if you assume that 5% of the electorate is well-informed on the relevant issues, you could argue that those 5% effectively decide the outcome of the election, whereas the votes of the other 95%, which are randomly distributed, cancel each other out.
6. Bryan Caplan, who credits Donald Wittman with “waking [him] from [his] dogmatic slumbers in political economy”, has compiled empirical evidence that voters are, in fact, systematically biased, thus concluding that Wittman’s argument is valid but not sound. In his book The Myth of the Rational Voter, Caplan identifies four main widespread biases about economics: “Make-work bias”, “Anti-foreign bias”, “Pessimistic bias”, “Anti-market bias”.
7. The term RATIONAL IRRATIONALITY, coined by Bryan Caplan, sounds all kinds of oxymoronic, but the two instances of “irrationality” in the phrase refer to two different kinds of rationality:
a. Epistemic rationality: “forming beliefs in truth-conductive ways”
b. Instrumental rationality: “choosing effective means to attain one’s goals, given one’s beliefs”
8. So while the idea of rational ignorance is that it is *instrumentally* rational to be ignorant, the idea of rational irrationality is that it is *instrumentally* rational to be *epistemically* irrational.
9. The costs of overcoming ignorance are generally high because studying the relevant issues takes time and effort. The costs of overcoming irrationality are generally high whenever people simply *enjoy* being irrational. Bryan Caplan argues that people have “preferences over beliefs”: there are beliefs that people just like to hold whether they are true or not, and giving them up would be emotionally costly to them – often extremely costly. So if the expected rewards from giving them up aren’t high enough, they won’t.
I think the solution is using the Crowdsourcing Utopia project as a form of direct democracy to identify the most cost-effective solution to each public policy problem that government is intended to solve.
Averaging guesses as to the effectiveness of a particular public policy solution to a problem would easily overcome plain ignorance as it would basically be seen as random noise and cancel itself out. The few people with the right answer would pile on top of each other so that you could identify the right answer. However, the problem of systemic bias remains.
The way to overcome this is to identify biased guessers and remove their guesses from the pool (aka filter out their biased guesses). This would be done using the equivalent of a captcha. Captcha are used to distinguish dumb robots from smarter humans. The captchas used in the crowdsourcing utopia project wouldn’t be just fuzzy strings of text. These captcha’s would be questions with a single, hard, correct and numerical answer that a biased person would have avoided integrating into their thought process in an attempt to avoid cognitive dissonance.
Let’s look at the 4 biases to be identified and filtered out.
Make-work bias
Anti-foreign bias
Pessimistic bias
Anti-market bias
Caplan refers to the anti-market bias as a “tendency to underestimate the benefits of the market mechanism.”[4] In Caplan’s view, the populace tends to view themselves as victims of the market, rather than participants of it. Corporations, and even small-scale suppliers, are seen as greedy monopolists that prey on the consumer. Caplan argues that all trade is a two-way street. Cheating people is bad for business and the existence of multiple firms offering similar products demonstrates there is competition, not monopoly power.